yes
Books to Read While the Algae Grow in Your Fur, February 2018
Attention
conservation notice: I have no taste. I also have no qualifications
to opine on the theory of measurement in psychology, the philosophy
of science, the law, race relations, or criminology.
- Joel Michell, Measurement in Psychology: A Critical History of a Methodological Concept
- Comments having passed the 1500 word mark, including long quotations, this
will have to be
a separate
review.
- H. P. Lovecraft, At the Mountains of Madness
- This is an umpteenth re-read, of course. (I tend to do them in the
winter.) This one made me want to read a history of subsequent Elder Thing
archaeology, where the mountains and the city were revisited during
the International
Geophysical Year, and it's become obvious that 99% of this is as much a
product of the discoverers' imagination and preconceptions as,
say, Arthur
Evans's views of the Minoans. (But that 1%...)
- ObLinkage: The Lovecraft Reread tackles AtMoM in three parts.
- Lauren Willig, The English Wife
- Mind candy historical mystery, set in New York and London just a bit before
1900. An interesting aspect of the writing is that here, as in her historical
romance novels, Willig uses two time-lines, where the characters in one
time-line are trying to discover what happened in the other. But in the
romances the time-lines are parallel, whereas here they converge. What this
signifies, I couldn't say.
- Peter Godfrey-Smith, Theory and Reality: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science
- I can easily say that this is the one of the best modern introductory books
on the philosophy of science I've ever read. (Another, of a very different
sort, is William
Poundstone's Labyrinths
of Reason.) It's presented roughly historically, beginning
with Logical
Positivism and moving forward, through Popper, Kuhn, such post-Kuhnians as
Lakatos, Feyerabend and Laudan, and classic 1970s/1980s "sociology of
scientific knowledge", before ending with a range of contemporary topics.
Throughout, Godfrey-Smith strikes a good balance between persuading the reader
that there are problems worth wrestling with, and that they're not hopeless.
- To the former: too many scientists, encountering issues from the philosophy
of science, find them pointless, or at most things which could be cleared up in
an afternoon with a little clear thinking and maybe some algebra.
(Occasionally this results in weird little cults
like self-styled
"strong inference", which is firmly put in its place here.) Godfrey-Smith
is very good at conveying how there are real issues here, which very smart
people have wrestled with, without coming to any truly satisfactory answers.
- This then raises the possibility that the exercise is futile, not because
it's unimportant but because it's doomed, that the problems are just too hard
for us. Against this, Godfrey-Smith is good at conveying how, if we're still
confused about questions like "When does observing something that a theory
predicts confirm the theory?", or "How can the social organization of
a scientific community support its cognitive goals?", we're at least
understanding the issues much better. (For example, it's become very clear
that social organization does matter.)
- This book is worthwhile reading for any scientist interested in
philosophical issues. It might be even more worthwhile for those
who aren't interested, but...
- --- Two thoughts which occurred to me while reading Godfrey-Smith's
discussion of how "naturalistic" philosophy of science is anti-foundationalist,
in the sense of eschewing the search for philosophical foundations for the
sciences which are somehow prior to the sciences themselves.
- Strong forms of this would say that such foundations are impossible or
undesirable. A weaker form, however, would compare the track-records of
philosophy and science, and say that it's rash to expect philosophy to
be more secure than (say) neurophysiology any time soon. (Where this would
leave,
say, social
psychology is a nice question.) I am not sure whether anyone has taken
this position within the philosophical literature, or even what it would be
called.
- Saying that we will use the results of scientific inquiry to understand
the process of scientific inquiry can sound like a vicious circle, but can
also, more reasonably, be just a self-consistency check. If our best
scientific understanding of the world and ourselves implied that scientific
inquiry was unreliable, we would have a real problem. Worries about science
being self-undermining are a a long-running theme in the history of the sort of
philosophy of science that Godfrey-Smith writes about, going back before the
Logical Positivists into the nineteenth century (see,
e.g., Leszek
Kolakowski's The Alienation of Reason / History of
Positivist Thought from Hume to the Vienna Circle and
his Husserl
and the Search for Certitude), and continues on today (naturally
in meme
format). Even if all naturalistic philosophy of science achieves is
showing that science doesn't undermine itself the way that
the more ambitious and
outrageous forms of sociology of knowledge do, this would be a real
accomplishment.)
§
- Richard Thompson
Ford, The Race Card: How Bluffing about Bias Makes Race Relations
Worse
- Let me spoil the ending:
No doubt some readers will wish to ask whether I really think
playing the race card is now the biggest racial justice issue this society
faces. No, I don't. I hope it's clear that I believe old-school bigotry
remains a severe social problem and that subtler and systemic racial
disadvantages --- even when they can't be blamed on "racists" --- are profound
social evils that demand redress. These are bigger problems than playing the
race card. But the race card is an impediment to dealing with these problems.
It distracts attention from larger social injustices. It encourages
vindictiveness and provokes defensiveness when open-mindedness and sympathy are
needed. It leads to an adversarial, tit-for-tat mind-set ("You're a bigot!"
"No, you're just playing the race card!") when a cooperative spirit of
dialogue is required.
The race card is symptomatic of a real crisis in the way we currently
think and talk about race: a crisis borne of our failure to keep up with
a changing social world, a crisis of social change and of intellectual
stasis. We need new intellectual tools and new language to deal with the new
realities of American racism. Thus far we've failed to develop them, so we
find ourselves increasingly unable to discuss issues of race intelligently
and convincingly. We find ourselves listening to and repeating the slogans
and catch-phrases of the past, whether or not they apply, like a catechism
that's long since lost its power to invoke or inspire, or like a curse that
damns guilty perpetrator and innocent bystander with indiscriminate
contempt. [p. 349]
- And this was in 2008! (Ford's skepticism about the Implicit Association
Test
is looking
pretty good these days. His confidence that open expressions of outright
racism have been driven to the fringes of American public
life, maybe
not so much.)
- More constructively, I found chapter 2's discussion of "racism by
analogy" thought-provoking, and chapter 3 on legal criteria for discrimination
and disparate impact quite eye-opening. §
- John Pfaff, Locked In: The True Causes of Mass Incarceration --- and How to Achieve Real Reform
- This is a thoughtful book about the causes of mass incarceration, and what
can and should be done to reverse it. I should say at the beginning that Pfaff
is as outraged as anyone about how many people we have in prison (or otherwise
subject to "corrections"), so that when Pfaff challenges elements of what he
calls the "standard story", it's not to minimize the disaster and disgrace,
it's to help efforts at reform actually improve things. I found a lot of
it convincing, but I should say up-front that I haven't tried to independently
check any of Pfaff's figures or calculations.
- The most convincing parts of the preliminary de-bunking are as follows:
- Private prisons are awful, but they are quantitatively too small to
account for mass incarceration. Also, the lobbying efforts of private prison
corporations are too small, and come too late in the surge in incarceration, to
explain it.
- Most of our prison population isn't there for drug offenses, or
non-violent offenses in general, but for violent crimes, and so undoing mass
incarceration will mean changing how we deal with those convicted of violence.
Pfaff presents this as a refutation of the idea that mass incarceration is due
to the war on drugs, which I think is a bit too hasty (as I will explain
below).
- Maximum legal prison sentences have gone way up, and longer prison terms
would naturally lead to more people being in prison. But this can't explain
most of the growth in incarceration, because the actual average length of time
served hasn't increase very much.
- It then behooves Pfaff to explain why, in his view, we have so many more
people in prison than we used to, even adjusting for population. Implicitly ---
this is a popular book and he does no explicit models here --- he works with a
"compartment" model, where the compartments or stages are something like:
\[
[\text{Commit crime}] \Rightarrow [\text{Arrested}] \Rightarrow [\text{Charged}] \Rightarrow [\text{Convicted}] \Rightarrow [\text{Prison}] \Rightarrow [\text{Release/Parole}]
\]
where at each stage before prison one might be diverted away (e.g., arrested
but not charged), and prison is of course of variable duration. The advantage
of approaching the question "why are so many people in prison?" this way is
that if you can track the number of people in each stage, and the flows of
people from one stage to the next, they have to add up: the number of
people in prison on 1 July 2018 will be the number who were in prison on 1 July
2017, plus those convicted and sentenced over the year, minus those released
over the year. (At the risk of being dis-respectful, I am counting deaths in
prison under "release".) Changing the proportions who go on from one stage to
the next changes the flows, and hence will accumulate over time to the number
of those in prison.
- Pfaff claims that the big change which drove up the number of people in
prison wasn't at the stage of being arrested, or convicted, or even the length
of time spent in prison, but rather in the proportion of those arrested who are
actually charged with a crime. This is a decision made by local
public prosecutors. If we believe Pfaff's numbers, this locates a key source
of the problem.
- Unfortunately, as he is at pains to say, we have very little systematic
information on prosecutors' offices and how they make their decisions. We do
know that they face a somewhat perverse set of incentives, in that declining to
charge someone who goes on to do something bad is electoral poison, but
charging someone who's really harmless has almost no downside (for the
prosecutor; it has plenty for the person charged, and their family and
community). Prosecutors also face little opposition from public defenders,
which is a big part of why almost all criminal charges are settled by plea
deals, not brought to trial. The whole business is a mess, with almost no
accountability (either to hierarchical superiors or to the democratic public),
and scarcely any systematic reporting. Pfaff does not attempt to say why any
of these issues should have gotten worse during this period, however.
- Popular books about policy or social problems usually have a last chapter
which talks about what to do about the issue. Pfaff follows this practice,
and, as usual, it's the weakest part of the book, because his proposals are so
much smaller than his own account of the scale of the problems. (Whether this
is better or worse than the alternative tradition, of proposing measures which
would solve the problem but also be totally unworkable, is a nice question.)
In no small part this is because he has fairly convincingly localized the
problem, but he's localized it not so much to a black box as to a mob of
3,000-odd ill-coordinated black boxes.
- --- I said above that I am not sure Pfaff is entirely fair to the
blame-the-drug-war camp; in particular, I think he ignores a fairly obvious
counter-argument. He attacks the idea that the growth in incarceration is a
result of the war on drugs, by pointing out that only a minority of those in
prison are there for non-violent drug offenses, while the majority are there
for violent crimes. Grant that this is true (as I said, I haven't checked his
figures*.) How much of that violence is
due to the war on drugs? Legal businesses get robbed, of course, and from
time to time one even reads of, say, dentists conspiring to assassinate rival
dentists, but this sort of thing is rare in trades where the law is available
to settle disputes and protect property. A criminalized but lucrative drug
trade, on the other hand, seems conducive to violence. Localizing the trade to
specific neighborhoods make those dangerous, law-less places, further inciting
violence (cf. Allen and
Leovy). Effects like these are hard to
quantify --- we can't just read them off from administrative data, as Pfaff
likes to do --- but they could be very important. I'm not sure where
this leaves us. §
-
*: One point which would be good to check is how possessing
of a firearm while committing another crime gets coded in these records. If
every drug-dealer who gets busted while also carrying a gun counts as
"violent", for example, that might make a substantial difference. (Or it might
not; that's why someone should check.) ^
- Danielle
Allen, Cuz: The Life and Times of Michael A.
- A memoir of the life, imprisonment and death of Allen's cousin Michael.
It's at once the specific story of a unique person and their family, and a
slice through what's gone wrong with our country*, that someone could be thrown in prison for eleven years
for some stupid crimes committed at fifteen (where Michael was the only one
hurt), ultimately setting his life on a path where, at age 29, his corpse was
found in a shot-up car on the street. Michael made bad choices, which Danielle
never shies from, but he made them in a foolishly, evilly un-forgiving context,
in a society which essentially threw his life away for no good reason,
and that is messed up. It's horribly, horribly sad, but beautifully
told. §
- Disclaimer: I know Prof. Allen, and have participated in a series
of workshops she organized
and contributed to
a book she
edited, but I feel under no obligation to write a positive notice of her
books.
- *: One of the things which makes this a complicated book is that it is
also, implicitly and in glimpses, the story of what has gone right
with our country that it now creates people like its author. ^
Books to Read While the Algae Grow in Your Fur;
The Beloved Republic;
Cthulhiana;
Minds, Brains, and Neurons;
Philosophy;
The Collective Use and Evolution of Concepts;
Pleasures of Detection, Portraits of Crime;
Tales of Our Ancestors;
Commit a Social Science
Posted at February 28, 2018 23:59 | permanent link