Major depression, qu'est-ce que c'est?
Attention conservation notice: 1100+ words on a
speculative scientific paper, proposing yet another reformation of
psychopathology. The post contains equations and amateur philosophy of
science. Reading it will not make you feel better. — Largely written in
2011 and then forgotten in my drafts folder, dusted off now because I chanced
across one of the authors
making related points.
As long-time readers may recall, I am a big fan
of Denny
Borsboom's work
on psychometrics,
and measurement problems more generally, so I am very pleased to be able to
plug this paper:
- Denny Borsboom, Angélique O. J. Cramer, Verena D. Schmittmann, Sacha Epskamp and Lourens J. Waldorp, "The Small World of Psychopathology",
PLOS ONE
6 (2011): e27407
[Data, code,
etc., not verified by me]
- Abstract: Mental disorders are highly comorbid: people having one disorder are likely to have another as well. We explain empirical comorbidity patterns based on a network model of psychiatric symptoms, derived from an analysis of symptom overlap in the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders-IV (DSM-IV).
- We show that a) half of the symptoms in the DSM-IV network are connected, b) the architecture of these connections conforms to a small world structure, featuring a high degree of clustering but a short average path length, and c) distances between disorders in this structure predict empirical comorbidity rates. Network simulations of Major Depressive Episode and Generalized Anxiety Disorder show that the model faithfully reproduces empirical population statistics for these disorders.
- In the network model, mental disorders are inherently complex. This explains the limited successes of genetic, neuroscientific, and etiological approaches to unravel their causes. We outline a psychosystems approach to investigate the structure and dynamics of mental disorders.
In the initial construction of the graph here, two symptoms are linked if
they are mentioned in the DSM as criteria for the same disorder. That is,
Borsboom et al. think of the DSM as a bipartite graph of symptoms and
disorders, and project down to just symptoms. (There is some data-tidying
involved in distinguishing symptoms and disorder.)
The small-world stuff leaves me cold — by this point it might be more
interesting to run across a large-world network — but the model
is intriguing. Each node (i.e., symptom) is a binary variable. The
probability that node $i$ gets activated at time $t$, $p_{it}$, is a function
of the number of activated neighbors, $A_{i(t-1)}$:
\[
p_{it} = a + (1-a) \frac{e^{b_i A_{i(t-1)}-c_i}}{(1-a)+e^{b_i A_{i(t-1)}-c_i}}
\]
In words, the more linked symptoms are present, the more likely it is for
symptom $i$ to be present to, but symptoms can just appear out of nowhere.
Statistically, this is a logistic regression: $b_i$ is how much symptom $i$
is activated by its neighbors in the graph, $c_i$ is a threshold specific to
that symptom, and $a$ controls the over-all rate of spontaneous symptom
appearance and disappearance. Using a very interesting data set
(the National
Comorbidity Survey Replication of about 9200 US adults), Borsboom et
al. in fact fixed the $b_i$ and $c_i$ parameters by running logistic
regressions. The $a$ parameter, which was kept the same across symptoms, was
tweaked to make the rate of spontaneous occurrence not too unreasonable.
What Borsboom et al. did with this model was to run it forward for
365 steps (i.e., a year), and then look at whether, in the course of the
previous year, it would have met the DSM criteria for major depression, and for
generalized anxiety disorder, and then repeat across multiple people. It did a
pretty good job of matching the prevalence of both disorders, and got their
co-morbidity a bit too high but not crazily so.
Now, as a realistic model, this is rubbish, for a host of reasons. Lots of
the edges have to be wrong; the edges should be directed rather than
undirected; the edges should be weighted; the logistic form owes more to what
psychologists are used to than any scientific plausibility. (Why should
psychopathology be a spin glass?)
The homogeneity of parameters across people could easily fail. And
yet even so it comes within spitting distance of reproducing the
observed frequencies of different conditions, and their co-morbidities.
Notice that despite this, there are no underlying disease variables in this
network, just symptoms. So why do we believe that there are
unitary disease entities? I can see at least three routes to that:
- Perhaps this symptom-network model simply fails to match the detailed
statistics of the data, while latent-disease-entity models can. This might be
a bit boring, perhaps, but it would be persuasive if one could show that no
model without the disease entities could work. (I find that dubious, but my
doubt is not evidence.)
- Alternately, one might appeal to causal autonomy. The temperature of a
gas, in a strong sense, amounts to the average kinetic energy of its molecules,
and one can
accurately simulate
gases at a molecular level without ever invoking the notion of temperature.
But if I manipulate the gas to have a certain temperature, then, very quickly,
the effects on pressure and volume, and even the velocity distribution of
individual molecules, is always (pretty much) the same, no matter how I bring
the temperature about. This is what lets us give sensible causal,
counter-factual accounts at the level of temperature, and thermodynamics more
generally.
(Cf. Glymour.)
Now, in the network model, we can imagine "giving someone" generalized
anxiety disorder, by activating some set of nodes which meets the DSM criteria
for that condition. There are actually multiple, only partially-overlapping
symptom sets which will do. In the network model, these different
instantiations of generalized anxiety disorder will have similar but not
identical consequences (for other symptoms, duration of the condition, response
to treatments, etc). If, in reality, it makes no difference how
someone comes to meet the criteria for generalized anxiety disorder, the
implications for the future are always the same, that would be a powerful
argument that the disorder is something real.
More medically: think how we
distinguish diabetes
into type 1
(the body doesn't make enough insulin)
and type 2
(the body doesn't respond properly to insulin). This is, I'd say, because they
differ greatly in their causal implications, but once you find yourself in one
of these classes, it makes little difference how you got there.
- It could be that a description in terms of higher-level entities like
depression allows for
a higher
efficiency of prediction than just sticking with symptoms. This notion
could even be made fairly
precise; it may also end up being the same as the second route.
Of course, it might be that to make any of these three defenses (or others
which haven't occurred to me) work properly, we'd have to junk our current set
of disorders and come up with others...
Minds, Brains, and Neurons;
Networks;
Enigmas of Chance
Posted at April 12, 2018 14:30 | permanent link